Display

Sunday, 11 October 2015

GEORG SIMMEL’S CONTRIBUTION TO THE RESOLUTION OF THE REALISM-NOMINALISM CONTROVERSY


Written by Michael, Michael Ntia


INTRODUCTION
Georg Simmel (1858-1918) is best known as a micro sociologist who played a significant role in the development of small-group research. Simmel's basic approach can be described as "methodological relationism," because he operates on the principle that everything interacts in some way with everything else. His essay on fashion, for example, notes that fashion is a form of social relationship that allows those who wish to conform to do so while also providing the norm from which individualistic people can deviate. Within the fashion process, people take on a variety of social roles that play off the decisions and actions of others. On a more general level, people are influenced by both objective culture (the things that people produce) and individual culture (the capacity of individuals to produce, absorb, and control elements of objective culture). Simmel believed that people possess creative capacities (more-life) that enable them to produce objective culture that transcends them. But objective culture (more-than-life) comes to stand in irreconcilable opposition to the creative forces that have produced it in the first place. (I. S. Kon, 1989)
THE CONCEPTS OF REALISM AND NOMINALISM
Nominalism is the philosophical view that abstract concepts, general terms, or universals have no independent existence but exist only as names. It also claims that various individual objects labeled by the same term have nothing in common but their name. In this view, it is only actual physical particulars that can be said to be real, and universals exist only post res, that is, subsequent to particular things.
Nominalism is best understood in contrast to philosophical or ontological realism. Philosophical realism holds that when people use general terms such as "cat" or "green," those universals really exist in some sense of "exist," either independently of the world in an abstract realm (as was held by Plato, for instance, in his theory of forms) or as part of the real existence of individual things in some way (as in Aristotle's theory of hylomorphism). The Aristotelian type of realism is usually called moderate realism. As a still another alternative, there is a school called conceptualism, which holds that universals are just concepts in the mind. (Bacon, John, 2008).

Loux (2001) goes on to note that the realist school claims that universals are real-they exist and are distinct from the particulars that instantiate them. Realists tend to argue that universals must be posited as distinct entities in order to account for various phenomena. For example, a common realist argument, arguably found in Plato, is that universals are required for certain general words to have meaning and for the sentences in which they occur to be true or false.

THE REALISM-NOMINALISM CONTROVERSY
Ever since the philosophers of ancient Greece there has been an ongoing debate about metaphysics, a debate that has moved through into the medieval era and even into modernity. The nature of this debate is whether the philosophic school of metaphysical realism; as upheld by Plato; or the philosophic school of nominalism; as upheld by Aristotle; shows us the true nature of reality.  On the one hand we have the belief that reality consist of things ordered by their abstract counterparts whilst on the other side of the debate it is believed that reality only consists of concrete things and to talk of such abstract ideas is an absurdity. (Klima, 2008).
ORIGIN OF THE REALISM-NOMINALISM CONTROVERSY
The origin of the realism-nominalism controversy can be traced back to the Middle Ages. It arose from a passage in Boethius's translation of Porphyry's Isagoge sive quinque voces ("Introduction to Aristotle's Categories"), which raised the problem of genera and species:
1)     as to whether they exist in nature or only in the mind;
2)     whether, if they exist in nature, they are corporeal or incorporeal; and
3)     Whether they exist outside sensible particular things or are realized in them.
Adherents to "realism" such as Bernard of Chartres, Saint Anselm, and William of Champeaux held, like Plato, that universals alone have substantial reality, existing ante res (prior to particular things). Proponents of "nominalism" such as Berengar of Tours and Roscellinus, however, objected that universals are mere names, existing post res (subsequent to particular things) without any reality. The controversy was prominent in the late eleventh and twelfth centuries, and the issue was not only philosophical but also theological because it was quite evident that while realism represented a more spiritual type of worldview, nominalism showed a more anti-spiritual view. Realism, which recognized the substantial reality of universals separable from this world, was favourable to the theological teachings of the Church on God, heaven, soul, afterlife, etc. Realism was also favourable to the Church's other teachings such as the Trinity, the Eucharist, and original sin, which presupposed the substantial existence of universals. By contrast, nominalism turned out to be less favourable to the teachings of the Church. For example, the nominalist Roscellinus argued that "God" is no more than a name, and that the divine reality is only found in the three different individuals called Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. In 1092, Roscellinus was condemned for being a tritheist. (Quine, 2006).

SIMMEL’S CONTRIBUTION TO THE RESOLUTION OF THE REALISM-NOMINALISM CONTROVERSY
In order to mediate between realism and nominalism, Georg Simmel suggested a position called "conceptualism." It rejects realism in favour of nominalism, when it says that universals have no substantial reality separable from the world of sensible things. However, it disagrees with nominalism, by maintaining that universals still exist as "concepts" in our minds, more than as mere names, thus being able to express real similarities in individual things themselves. But this position of conceptualism seems to be letting us come back to the same debate over the relationship of universals and individuals—albeit at a level—instead of answering it.
Johnson cited in John, Essien (2010) summarizes Simmel’s contribution towards resolving the controversy thus:
“Simmel focuses on the process of interaction as a sine qua non for the establishment of society. To him, society emerges as a result of reciprocal interaction. His image of the nature of social reality is, like that of Durkheim, more than the sum of the individuals making it up. Patterns of interaction link individuals together into one whole. Nevertheless, Simmel realized that society cannot exist as an objective reality independent of its members. Simmel’s bridge-building approach strikes a balance between the opposing claims of those who believe only on individuals as real (nominalism) and those who believe that society is real and independent of the individuals who make it up (realists).

CONCLUSION
This paper has been able to x-ray the meaning of realism as well as nominalism. We have also examined the controversy that emanated as a result of varying positions on the subject of concern. Simmel, in his philosophic position attempted to do justice to the antitheses that have occupied philosophers since the pre-Socratics. He succeeded in doing this by proposing conceptualism which admits the existence within us of abstract and universal concepts, but it holds that we do not know whether or not the mental objects have any foundation outside our minds or whether in nature the individual objects possess distributively and each by itself the realities which we conceive as realized in each of them. The concepts have an ideal value; they have no real value, or at least we do not know whether they have a real value.



REFERENCES
Armstrong, D.M. (1968). A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge &
            Kegan Paul; New York: Humanities Press

Bacon, John (2008). "Tropes", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N.

Feibleman, James K. "Nominalism." In Dictionary of Philosophy, edited by
            Dagobert D. Runes, 211. Nominalism - New World Encyclopedia

I. S. Kon, (1989) A History of Classical Sociology. Moscow: Progress Publishers.

John D. O., Essien B. S. (2010). History Social Thought and Social
            Philosophy. Ibadan: Panse Publishers Limited.

Johnson, D.P (1981). Sociology Theory. New York: John Wiley and Sons.

Loux, Michael J. (2001). "The Problem of Universals" in Metaphysics: Contemporary
            Readings, Michael J. Loux (ed.), N.Y.: Routledge, pp. 313.

Quine, W.V. (2006). From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-Philosophical Essays,
            2nd ed. Harvard University Press.

Woozley, A.D. (1967) "Universals." In The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by
            Paul Edwards, vol. 8, 194-206. New York & London: Macmillan.



No comments:

Post a Comment